• Dutch
  • Frisian
  • Saterfrisian
  • Afrikaans
Show all
2.1.General observations
readmore
[+]  I.  Complementation of nouns: complements and modifiers

Section 1.1.2 has shown that the noun phrase can be divided into two subdomains, the NP- and the DP-domain: the NP-domain is headed by the noun and determines the denotation of the noun phrase, whereas the DP-domain is headed by a determiner or a quantifier/numeral and determines the referential and/or quantificational properties of the noun phrase. Thus, the internal structure of the noun phrase as a whole can be represented as in (1), in which Determiner (D) and Noun (N) are the heads of the projections DP and NP, respectively, and where the dots indicate the possible positions of other elements. In this chapter, as well as in Chapter 3, we will concentrate on the projection of the noun, that is, the NP-domain.

1
[DP ... D ... [NP ... N ...]]

Each NP contains an obligatory head N and, optionally, one or more other elements, which can be further categorized according to their function, i.e., according to whether they function as complements or as restrictive modifiers. Complements are elements whose presence is required by the semantics of the head noun; the idea is that these complements are obligatory arguments of the nominal head, comparable to the complements of verbs. Restrictive modifiers, on the other hand, are not required by the semantics of the head.
      Complements are generally closer to the nominal head than the restrictive (as well as the non-restrictive) modifiers. Example (2a) illustrates this for the nominal complement tomaten'tomatoes' and the adjectival modifier gebruikelijk'usual' in prenominal position, example (2b) for the PP-complement van Jan'of Jan' and the PP-modifier in het ziekenhuis'in hospital' in postnominal position, and example (2c) for the clausal complement dat Jan ziek geworden was and the restrictive relative clause dat net binnenkwam in postnominal position.

2
a. Het gebruikelijke tomaten gooien bleef niet uit.
  the  customary  tomatoes  throwing  remained  not  prt.
  'The customary throwing of tomatoes followed.'
b. de langdurige behandeling van Jan in het ziekenhuis
  the  protracted  treatment  of Jan  in the hospital
c. het bericht dat Jan ziek geworden was dat net binnenkwam
  the report  that  Jan ill  become  has  that  just  arrived
  'the report that Jan has become ill that just arrived'

These word order facts lead to the generalization in (3), according to which complements and modifiers are inserted at different levels within NP: complements are immediate sisters of the head noun, whereas modifiers are adjuncts inserted at some higher level in the NP. According to this assumption, the structures of the noun phrases in (2) are as indicated in (4).

3
Generalization I: Complements are closer to the nominal head of the NP than modifiers; the former are immediate sisters of the head noun, whereas the latter are adjoined at some higher lever within NP.
4
a. het [NP gebruikelijke [tomaten gooien]]
b. de [NP langdurige [behandeling van Jan] in het ziekenhuis]
c. het [NP [bericht dat Jan ziek geworden was] dat net binnenkwam]

The difference between complements and restrictive modifiers is often hard to determine, as the two may be categorially identical. This is not so much the case in prenominal position, where the modifier typically takes the form of an AP and the complement takes the form of a noun phrase or a PP, as in (5a), but this problem does occur in postnominal position, where complements and modifiers both may take the form of a PP or a clause, as in (5b&c).

5
a. [NP AP-modifier [ NP/PP-complement N]]
b. [NP [N PP-complement] PP-modifier]
c. [NP [N Clausal complement] Clausal modifier]

Although the present chapter will be mainly concerned with complements, it is necessary to first address more extensively the difference between complements and modifiers: Section 2.2.1 will discuss the difference between prepositional complements and modifiers in (5b), and Section 2.3.3 the difference between clausal complements and modifiers in (5c). Modification within the NP will, however, be the main topic of Chapter 3.

[+]  II.  Nouns as predicates

The term complementation is usually associated with the verbal domain. Verbs have argument structures, specifying the number and thematic roles of their arguments. Arguments of verb must be divided into (i) internal arguments or complements and (ii) externalarguments. The former in a sense complete the predicate, as a result of which it can be predicated of the latter. In the lexical frames in (6), the external argument is underlined in order to distinguish it from the complements. The semantic arguments of the verb are normally realized as syntactic arguments: internal arguments generally surface as the objects of the verb, whereas the external argument normally corresponds to the subject.

6
Predicate
Example
a. lopenV (Agent):
  walk
a'. [Jan]Agent [loopt]Pred
  Jan   walks
b. lezenV (Agent, Theme):
  read
b'. [Marie]Agent [koopt een krant]Pred
  Marie   buys a newspaper
c. gevenV (Agent, Theme, Recipient)
  give
c'. [Jan]Agent [geeft Marie een boek]Pred
  Jan   gives Marie a book

Nouns may function as predicates as well, and are therefore also able to take arguments. This is shown in (7), in which the nominal noun phrase genie'genius' is predicated of the noun phrase Jan, which therefore functions as the external argument. Since the usual labels for semantic roles are especially created for expressing the roles of the arguments in the event structure denoted by verbal predications, we will simply refer to the external argument of nouns as the referent (Ref), that is, the entity to which the property denoted by the nominal (or adjectival) predicate applies.

7
genieN (Ref)
a. [Jan]Ref is [een genie]Pred.
  Jan  is  a genius
b. Ik vind [Jan]Ref [een genie]Pred.
  consider   Jan   a genius

The syntactic mapping of the external arguments of nouns is more complicated than that of verbs. If the noun is used as the head of a nominal predicate in a copular or vinden-construction, the mapping is rather straightforward: in (7), for example, the external argument corresponds to the noun phrase Jan, which functions respectively as the subject and the object of the clause. However, if the noun is used as the head of a noun phrase in argument position, it typically tends to be syntactically avalent: rather than behaving like a predicate with one or more arguments, the noun phrase it is part of acts as an argument of some other predicate. Correspondingly, such noun phrases do not denote a property, but typically have a referential function: they identify the entity or set of entities about which something is predicated. In (8), for instance, the noun phrase de man has the same function as Jan in (7), that is, it acts as the external argument of the nominal predicate.

8
a. [De man]Ref is [een genie]Pred.
  the man  is  a genius
b. Ik vind [de man]Ref [een genie]Pred.
  consider   the man   a genius

This does not mean, however, that nouns heading a noun phrase in argument position do not have a predicative function: such nouns can be said to predicate something of their referential argument, that is, of the entity or set of entities referred to by means of the noun phrase. The noun phrase een man in (9a), for example, can be paraphrased as ∃x man (x): there is an entity x such that the predicate man applies to x. Correspondingly, (9a) is normally assigned the semantic interpretation in (9b), which involves the conjunction of two predicates: there is an entity x such that the predicates man and walking in the street both apply to x.

9
a. Er loopt een man op straat.
  there  walks  a man  in the.street
b. ∃x (man (x) & walks on the street (x))

The discussion above, which is based on Williams (1981), shows that nouns always have an external argument, but that this argument is not syntactically expressed if the noun is the head of a noun phrase functioning as the syntactic argument of some other predicate, as in (9). The external argument of the noun can (and must) be syntactically realized only if the noun is heading a noun phrase that syntactically functions as a predicate, as in (7). This is given as generalization II in (10).

10
Generalization II: The external argument (Ref) of a noun cannot be syntactically realized unless the noun syntactically functions as a predicate in, for instance, a copular or a vinden-construction.
[+]  III.  Complementation of non-derived nouns

Complementation is not a typical property of non-derived nouns. There are, however, at least two classes of basic nouns that normally require the presence of an argument. The first is the class of relational nouns, which includes kinship nouns like vader'father', broer'brother', nicht'niece', and nouns denoting physical properties of objects like vorm'shape', gewicht'weight' or kleur'color'; see Section 1.2.3 for more examples. These relational nouns can successfully fulfill their referential function only if related to some other entity. This is illustrated in (11a) for the noun vader: this example is only acceptable if a noun phrase is present carrying the “child” role assigned by the noun vader. Another example is given in (11b): the noun vorm'shape' cannot refer independently but requires the syntactic realization of the noun phrase referring to a physical object that has some shape. Note that in accordance with generalization II in (10), the “Ref” role only needs to be expressed syntactically if the noun phrase headed by vader functions syntactically as a predicate. Complementation of the relational nouns will be discussed more extensively in Section 2.2.2.

11
VADERN (Ref, child)
a. [Jan]Ref is [de vader *?(van Marie)]Pred
  Jan  is  the father     of Marie
a'. Ik ontmoette gisteren de vader *?(van Marie).
  met  yesterday  the father      of Marie
b. Jan bewonderde de vorm *?(van de ijsberg).
  Jan admired  the shape    of the iceberg

Other non-derived nouns that may take complements are the so-called picture and story nouns. Some examples are given in (12): in (12a), the noun schets'sketch' assigns a theme role to de Amstel (it is the object depicted) and an agent role to Rembrandt (he is the maker of the painting); in (12b) something similar holds for the story noun gedicht. Complementation of the picture/story nouns will be discussed more extensively in Section 2.2.5.

12
a. schetsN (Ref, Agent, Theme)
a'. Rembrandts schets van de Amstel
  Rembrandtʼs  sketch  of the Amstel
b. gedichtN (Ref, Agent, Theme)
b'. Boons gedicht over de kleine Eva
  Boonʼs  poem  about the little Eva
[+]  IV.  Derived nouns: inheritance of argument structure

Whereas non-derived nouns typically do not take complements, derived nouns do. The arguments of these derived nouns are typically “inherited” from the input stem. Take as an example the transitive verb behandelen'to treat' and the noun behandeling'treatment', which is derived from the former by adding the suffix -ing. As is illustrated in (13), the verb and the noun can take the same arguments: an agent and a theme. The main difference between the verbal and the nominal predicate is that, whereas the agent is the external argument of the verb, it is an internal argument of the noun: the external argument of the noun is assigned the “Ref” role. In accordance with Generalization II in (10), the argument bearing the agent role can be expressed within the noun phrase (whereas the “Ref” role need not be syntactically expressed).

13
Transitive
a. behandelenV (Agent, Theme)
  to treat
a'. Jan behandelde de patiënt.
  Jan treated  the patient
b. behandelingN (Ref, Agent, Theme)
  treatment
b'. Jans behandeling van de patiënt
  Janʼs  treatment  of the patient

The same thing applies to nouns derived from intransitive verbs, as shown by example (14). Here, too, the agent argument of the verb is inherited by the noun as an internal argument, with the addition of a new external argument that is assigned the “Ref” role. Again, the argument bearing the agent role can be expressed within the noun phrase.

14
Intransitive
a. huilenV (Agent)
  to cry
a'. De kinderen huilen.
  the children  cry
b. huilenN (Ref, Agent)
  crying
b'. het huilen van de kinderen
  the crying of the children

      In the nominalizations in (13) and (14), the external argument of the verb is transformed into an internal argument of the derived noun. In the case of deverbal person nouns derived by the suffix -er, however, the external argument of the verb is similar to the external argument of the noun: the argument assigned the “Ref” role of the derived noun schrijver'writer' in (15b) corresponds to the argument that is assigned the agent role by the predicate een boek schrijven in (15a). In accordance with this, the argument that corresponds to the argument assigned the agent role by the verb cannot be expressed within the noun phrase; it can only be realized as the subject or the object of a clause in which the noun phrase is used as a syntactic predicate.

15
Deverbal -er nouns:
a. schrijvenV (Agent, Theme)
  to write
a'. Jan schrijft een boek.
  Jan writes  a book
  'Jan is writing a book.'
b. schrijverN (Ref, Theme)
  writer
b'. de schrijver van het boek
  the writer of the book

      Inheritance of argument structures can also found with deadjectival nouns In example (16), for instance, the external argument of hoog, which we call “RefA” in order to distinguish it from the “RefN” role of the noun, functions as an internal argument of the noun hoogte'height'.

16
a. hoogA (RefA)
  high
a'. De toren is hoog.
  the tower  is high
b. hoogteN (RefN, RefA)
  height
b'. de hoogte van de toren
  the height of the tower

Since adpositions cannot readily be used as the input of a nominalization process, we will not discuss these here; see 1.3.4 for examples.
      This subsection has shown that nominalization generally involves the internalization of the external argument of the input form; only if we are dealing with a deverbal noun derived by -er does the external argument of the verb seem to correspond to the external argument of the derived noun. This is expressed as generalization III in (17).

17
Generalization III: Nominalization implies the internalization of the external argument of the input form, unless we are dealing with a deverbal er-noun.
[+]  V.  The form of the arguments

This subsection discusses the various ways in which the internal arguments of a noun can be realized. Within the verbal domain, agentive arguments appear as nominative noun phrases in active clauses, and, optionally, as agentive door-PPs in passive clauses. Arguments with the semantic function of theme normally appear as accusative noun phrases in active clauses and as nominative noun phrases in passive clauses. Arguments with the semantic function of goal/benefactive can be realized as a dative noun phrase or as an aan/voor-PP. The remaining arguments are realized as PPs. However, given that a noun normally does not assign case, we expect that its internal arguments are typically realized as PPs. As will be shown in the following subsections, this is indeed possible, but it is certainly not the case that this exhausts the possibilities.

[+]  A.  Realization of the internal argument as a PP or genitive noun phrase

The discussion in this subsection will show that there are often two ways to realize the agentive and theme arguments of the noun: they can be expressed by means of either a postnominal PP or a prenominal genitive noun phrase or possessive pronoun. Arguments carrying other thematic roles are always realized by means of a PP.

[+]  1.  Realization of the internal argument as a van-PP

A theme argument of a deverbal noun that corresponds to a direct object of the input verb can be realized by means of a van-PP, as shown by (18a), and the same thing holds for the theme argument of a picture noun like schilderij'painting' in (18b). The theme argument of a story noun like gedicht'poem' in (18c), however, is preceded by the preposition over'about'.

18
Theme arguments of deverbal nouns and picture/story nouns
a. de behandeling van JanTheme
  the treatment  of Jan
b. het schilderij van de AmstelTheme
  the painting  of the Amstel
c. het gedicht over/??van de kleine EvaTheme
  the poem  about  the little Eva

      The agentive argument of a deverbal noun can also be realized as a postnominal van-PP, as is shown by (19a&b). It should be noted, however, that this leads to a marked result if the input verb is transitive, in which case the argument is preferably realized as an agentive door-PP, as is shown by the (c)-examples in (19).

19
Agentive arguments of deverbal nouns
a. het gehuil van JanAgent
  the crying  of Jan
b. het zoeken van JanAgent naar de waarheidTheme
  the looking  of Jan  for the truth
c. ?? de behandeling van de dokterAgent van JanTheme
  the treatment  of the doctor  of Jan
c'. de behandeling van JanTheme door de dokterAgent
  the treatment  of Jan  by the doctor

      The examples in (20) show that the agentive argument of a picture/story noun can also be realized as a van-PP, and those in (21) show that the same thing holds for the internal arguments of relational nouns.

20
Agentive arguments of picture/story nouns
a. het schilderij van RembrandtAgent
  the painting  of Rembrandt
  'the painting by Rembrandt'
b. het gedicht van Louis-Paul BoonAgent
  the poem  of Louis-Paul Boon
  'the poem by Louis-Paul Boon'
21
Related arguments of relational nouns
a. de vader van Marie
  the father  of Marie
b. de vorm van de ijsberg
  the shape  of the iceberg
[+]  2.  Realization of the internal argument as a possessive pronoun/genitive noun phrase

Internal arguments of a noun that can be realized as van-PPs can often also be realized as prenominal possessive pronouns or genitive noun phrases (with the genitive suffix s). The examples in (19) and (20), for instance, alternate with the primeless examples in (22) and (23), in which the agent is realized in prenominal position as a genitive noun phrase. Since noun phrases like de dokter'the doctor' in (22b) normally give rise to a marked result if they are used as a genitive possessor (see the discussion below (25)), we also give examples with a prenominal possessive pronoun.

22
Agentive arguments of deverbal nouns
a. JansAgent gehuil
  Janʼs  crying
a'. zijnAgent gehuil
  his  crying
b. ? de doktersAgent behandeling van Jan `
  the doctorʼs  treatment of Jan
b'. zijnAgent behandeling van Jan
  his  treatment of Jan
c. JansAgent zoeken naar de waarheid
  Janʼs looking for the truth
c'. zijnAgent zoeken naar de waarheid
  his  looking  for the truth
23
Agentive arguments of picture/story nouns
a. RembrandtsAgent schilderij
  Rembrandtʼs  painting
a'. zijnAgent schilderij
  his  painting
b. Louis-Paul BoonsAgent gedicht
  Louis-Paul Boonʼs  poem
b'. zijnAgent gedicht
  his  poem

      Example (24) shows that a theme argument can also be realized as a prenominal genitive noun phrase or possessive pronoun. This prenominal realization is, however, restricted to theme arguments that can be realized as van-PPs; since the theme argument of a story noun is normally expressed by an over-PP, (25b) is unacceptable under the intended non-agentive reading.

24
a. Jans/zijnTheme behandeling
  Janʼs/his  treatment
b. Jans/zijnTheme foto
  Janʼs/his  photo
25
a. het gedicht over de kleine EvaTheme
  the poem  about  the little Eva
b. * de kleine Evaʼs/haarTheme gedicht
  the little Evaʼs/her  poem

      There are additional restrictions on the realization of the agent/theme argument as a genitive noun phrase or a possessive pronoun. In fact, the prenominal position in (24) is only accessible to (i) possessive pronouns and (ii) a limited set of +human nouns including proper nouns and a number of kinship and professional nouns; see Section 5.2.2.1 and Section 5.2.2.5, sub I, for more details. This is shown by the fact that whereas the primeless (a)-examples in (26) and (27) alternate with the primed ones, the primeless (b)-examples do not.

26
a. de foto van Jan Theme
  the photo of Jan
a'. JansTheme foto
  Janʼs  picture
b. de foto van de AmstelTheme
  the photo of the Amstel
b'. * de AmstelsTheme foto
  the Amstelʼs  photo
27
a. de vader van Marie
  the father of Marie
a'. Maries vader
  Marieʼs  father
b. de vorm van de berg
  the shape of the mountain
b'. * de bergʼs vorm
  the mountainʼs  shape

      The fact that, in principle, the agentive and the theme argument of a noun can both be expressed by means of a postnominal van-PP or as a prenominal genitive noun phrase or possessive pronoun provides evidence in favor of generalization III in (17) that the two must be considered on a par as internal arguments of the noun.

[+]  3.  Realization of the internal argument as a door-PP

The option of using a door-PP is restricted to agentive arguments of deverbal nouns, as is illustrated for deverbal nouns based on an intransitive and transitive verb, in (28a) and (28b) respectively.

28
Agentive arguments of deverbal nouns
a. (?) het gehuil door de kinderen
  the crying  by the children
b. de behandeling van JanTheme door de arts